CHAPTER 5 Uncanny (Wo)Man: The Home/Secrets of Psychoanalysis Section 3 "The Uncanny" and Superstition Early in "The Uncanny," Freud praises Jentsch, a predecessor on the subject of das Unheimlich, for laying "stress on the obstacle [to writing about the uncanny] presented by the fact that people vary so very greatly in their sensitivity to this quality of feeling" (XVII 220). Then Freud makes the following statement and disingenuously frames it as a confession: The writer of the present contribution, indeed, must himself plead guilty to a special obtuseness in the matter, where extreme delicacy of perception would be more in place. It is long since he has experienced or heard of anything which has given him an uncanny impression, and he must start by translating himself into that state of feeling, by awakening in himself the possibility of experiencing it. (ibid.)I find it intriguing that Freud would argue that he could actively make himself open to feeling the uncanny. More evidence of his sense of mastery over this feelingto which by definition one would be passivelies in his later claim that the type of uncanny feeling associated with animistic beliefs does not concern repressiona process to which one is passivebut a process of "surmounting," where one would be a more active participant. Freud puts himself in the category of someone who has gotten beyond sensitivity to this feeling because he has actively rid himself of those remnants, the ghostly remains, of animistic beliefs that cause the uncanny: "anyone who has completely and finally rid himself of animistic beliefs will be insensible to this type of the uncanny" (XVII 248). Perhaps Freud felt he had also "surmounted" the other type of the uncanny, which involves infantile complexes, by way of his self analysis, where Freud, via a certain activity, is able to subvert his own theory of ones passive relation to the unconscious. Of course, Freuds own works, and those of his biographers, are filled with clues that, far from being insensitive to this type of feeling, Freud was acutely sensitive to them, and to the conflicts such beliefs would cause for the leader of a movement that is trying to establish itself as a science and that often must do so by fending off accusations that psychoanalysis is akin to, if not an example of, occultism. According to Jones, Freuds "wish to believe [in occultism] fought hard with the warning to disbelieve" (Gay88 444). Jones writes the following in his most orthodox biography of Freud: The extent to which a given superstitious belief is accepted by the mind is usually one of degree, and it is often very hard to ascertain to what extent the person "really" gives credence to it. It is a common experience to get the reply when someone is questioned on the point: "No, I dont really believe it, but all the same it is very odd." Acceptance and rejection are both operative . Freud was no exception in this respect, and he would himself have not found it easy at times to say whether he accepted a given belief of this order or not. (3: 379)This simultaneous "acceptance and rejection" would be a form of Freudian disavowal and a similar alogic as in Freuds conception of the fetish. Given the definitive statements he makes, such as the one above about his insensitivity to uncanny feelings, it seems that Freud actually found it quite easy to disavow his superstitious beliefs, even though he would argue at other times they were either partially true (aspects of occultism) or wholly true (telepathy). At times he would even vehemently attack superstitions, occultism, and religion as if they were the enemy in a war. According to Peter Gay, Freuds "view of religion as the enemy was wholly shared by the first generation of psychoanalysts" (Gay88 533n), and this view was extended to superstitions and occultism. Those beliefs of Freuds that other psychoanalysts would classify as superstitious in other people, as Freud would also do in his more secular materialist moments, might be compared with his Lamarckian mythology of phylo-"genetics": both were somewhat suppressed by Freud and the psychoanalytic orthodoxy, and both have a similar relation to science and to the issue of determinacy versus contingencythat is, both superstition and Freuds phylo-"genetics" are ultimately deterministic beliefs. An example of Freuds superstitious beliefs is given in The Psychopathology of Everyday Life, where Freud finds a hidden meaning regarding the number 2,467, which he had written to Fliess regarding his guess at how many mistakes The Interpretation of Dreams contained. After relating the number to the retirement of a general he knew, and then the manipulation of the number of years he had until his own retirement, subtracting, then dividing he came up with the number sixty seven, and interpreted this as a wish to have just a few more years of lifethat is, not to die at age sixty two, the age his father had died, and the age he was sure he would die. Seven or so years after writing this passage in Psychopathology, Freud would begin writing "The Uncanny." He would write over a period from when he was about fifty eight to sixty three, including this passage: If we take another class of things, it is easy to see that there, too, it is only this factor of involuntary repetition which surrounds what would otherwise be innocent enough with an uncanny atmosphere, and forces upon us the idea of something fateful and inescapable when otherwise we should have spoken only of "chance." For instance, we naturally attach no importance to the event when we hand in an overcoat and get a cloakroom ticket with the number, let us say, 62; or when we find that our cabin on a ship bears that number. But the impression is altered if two such events, each in itself indifferent, happen close togetherif we come across the number 62 several times in a single day, if we begin to notice that everything which has a numberaddresses, hotel rooms, compartments in railway trainsinvariably has the same one, or at all events one which contains the same figures. We do feel this to be uncanny. And unless a man is utterly hardened and proof against the lure of superstition, he will be tempted to ascribe a secret meaning to this obstinate recurrence of a number; he will take it, perhaps, as an indication of the span of life allotted to him. (XVII 237-8)Did Freud see himself as such a hardened man, with "a special obtuseness in the matter"? Or did he see himself as a less special man, one who would be tempted to "ascribe a secret meaning"? The "lure of superstition" is not to have to speak of "chance." Freuds quotes around "chance" suggest a certain disdain for what would be this more common sense conclusion. Freud suggests that what is difficult is not the hardening of oneself, but the acceptance of a certain fate and the "involuntary repetition" it enforcesthat is, ultimately giving up a certain bad faith of having choice and of there being chance. Fates lure for Freud is its determinism. For Freud, the evidence of the 2,467 example is, not necessarily the truth of Fate and related superstitious beliefs, but the proof that there is no chance in psychic reality, and that there is nothing beyond his theory of wish-fulfillment: nothing beyond the PP and its/his mastery. But Freuds point with the number sixty in "The Uncanny" goes beyond psychic determinism. Freud wrote this essay right after the Wolf Man case where he struggled so with the contingencies of "external reality," and the problems these contingencies created for the development of his masterplot. This is not an example of unconscious fantasy filtering out other numbers (anticathexis of sorts) and investing in the one number (hypercathexis), which would be a typical psychoanalytic interpretation, if not simply a Freudian one. For the number to indicate a destined "span of life allotted to him," of course, there would have to be Fate: a cosmological determinism. The imbrication of themes we find abovethemes of a general determinism, a powerful Other that constitutes ones fate, ones passivity to this Other, chance, ones connection to a parent (in this case, the father), and deathare repeated in Freuds later essay, "Femininity," with respect to the childs relation to the mother. Freud writes, after discussing one of the childs early reproaches of the mother, "that it never gets over the pain of losing its mothers breast" (XXII 122). He then claims a universality of the fantasy of being poisoned by the mother: The fear of being poisoned is also probably connected with the withdrawal of the breast. Poison is nourishment that makes one ill. Perhaps children trace back their early illnesses too to this frustration. A fair amount of intellectual education is a prerequisite for believing in chance; primitive people and uneducated ones, and no doubt children as well, are able to assign a ground for everything that happens. Perhaps originally it was a reason on animistic lines. Even to-day in some strata of our population no one can die without having been killed by someone elsepreferably by the doctor. And the regular reaction of a neurotic to the death of someone closely connected with him is to put the blame on himself for having caused the death. (ibid.)First of all, Freud would often claim the truth of what he had formerly posited as a childrens theory, as he did with castration. Freud associates truth with what is archaic and primitive. Another example would be the childhood belief in "the omnipotence of thought" and Freuds belief in telepathy (see Freuds essay, "Psychoanalysis and Telepathy" (XVIII)). What I want to draw attention to here, however, is the imbrication for Freud of animistic beliefs and the mother, and of science and the father: Freuds gendering of belief systems. As Freud argues, believing in Fate, in a Destiny where there is no chance, would be a primitive belief of "Man/man." Science, on the other hand, teaches chance; it is a mature belief system one hopefully grows into. As one must do with ones connection to the mother, one must "surmount" animistic beliefs. Soon after the passage above, Freud argues that the "wish to get the longed-for penis" may be sublimated by a woman in the form of a capacity "to carry on an intellectual profession" (XXII 125). Clearly the sciences and intellectualism, and therefore a belief in chance, are associated for Freud with masculinity and by extension with the father, whereas an animistic and primitive belief in determinism is associated with the primitive or archaic connection with the mother and by extension with femininity. Like Derridas reading of Platos undecidable use of "pharmakon" as poison/cure, determinism is the poison/nourishment of the mothers milkthough we might wonder why Freud strangely claims that all poison is nourishment. The poison of determinism for Freud is the separation it causes from the position of masculine science; the nourishment is the potential sense of mastery it provides. Here, from a phallocentric perspective, the figures of both parents are simultaneously "phallic" and castrating. As Plato wrote about the dangers of writingneeding writing itself, and its metaphors, to further his phonocentric and logocentric beliefsFreud at times disparages the determinism of superstition as he works hard to create a masterplot of totalizing cause and effect. Freuds repeated return to the themes of the occult and telepathy can be read as Freud trying to have the "nourishment" of both animistic beliefs (determinism) and the "nourishment" of science (the legitimate, masculine authority), the nourishment of both the mother and the father, without the poison of either: femininity/primitiveness and chance, respectively. Freud would associate death with both poisons. He was like a man with two gods: one maternal and one paternal. But both are viewed from a phallocentric position, and in fact the phallic mother might be a compromise figuration of such a conflicted belief. The connections between the uncanny, superstition, chance, difference, and the figure of woman are revealed in Freuds treatment of disavowal as a simultaneous belief-disbelief, as the primary defense mechanism of the fetishist against "external reality." Freuds relationship to superstition and the uncanny can be seen as an example of the "Splitting of the Ego in the Process of Defence" (XXIII), according to his 1938 essay title, and concerns the disavowal of perception. The phallic archetype of "perception" here is the perception of the "reality" of womans castration. A secret of Freuds 1938 essay is that splitting is the defense of (op)positionality in the "face to face" with an Other that is irreducible to a One via twos, threes, absences, presences, theses, antitheses, or the kind of Aufhebung Hegel defined as preserving both the thesis and antithesis, rather than negating either or both. This is the type of Aufhebung the fetishist tries to realize: a preservation of both the phallic mother and the mother of castration (castrated and therefore potentially castrating). The fetishist cannot decide between giving up the jouissance the oedipally individuated subject might associate with the former (being One with Fate or God) or the possibility of the position of scientific master the latter holds out as lure through the reduction of woman to castration-truth where lack has its place (the hom(m)osexual One). We might say that there are three demons under the employ of psychoanalysis: "external reality," ontogeny, and woman. With the determinism of Fate associated with the phallic mother, the chance of "external reality" cannot disrupt the movement toward the totality of the masterplot. The phallic mother, however, is a mother, and therefore does not allow for a simply masculine position of power. With a masterplot based on primal narratives free of all-powerful mother figures, it can position a masculine One. But this masterplot lacks the cosmological determinism of an "external reality" where ontogeny is determined by Fate: it contains the chance of what is figured from a phallocentric perspective as paternal science. Freudian psychoanalysis attempts to reduce what is totally other and full of contingency to (op)positionality and determinism via the trope of castration. Behind the "three demons" mentioned above is the Other, even though these three demons to the One are also employed as dissimulators: they all are the products of idealist binaries. Chance is rarely if ever used by Freud, and yet it haunts psychoanalysis. Ironically, Freuds work is full of the very animistic beliefs he claims to have surmounted: for example, the omnipotence of thought (privileging of psychical reality, the truth of telepathy) and what he calls the displacement of the symbol for the thing itself. The latter is especially evident in Freuds treatment of castration as a reality. According to Laplanche and Pontalis, the splitting of the ego of disavowal concerns "the primary defense consisting of a radical repudiation and the notion that such a mechanism bears specifically upon the reality of castration" (Lap67 119). This last point is without doubt the one which gives us the best key to the Freudian idea of disavowal, but it also brings us to reopen and extend the questions which that idea raises. If the disavowal of castration is the prototypeand perhaps even the originof the other kinds of disavowal of reality [such as superstition], we are forced to ask what Freud understands by the "reality" of castration or by the perception of this reality. If it is the womans "lack of penis" that is disavowed, then it becomes difficult to talk in terms of perception of reality, for an absence is not perceived as such, and it only becomes real in so far as it is related to a conceivable presence. If, on the other hand, it is castration itself which is repudiated, then the object of disavowal would not be a perceptioncastration never being perceived as suchbut rather a theory designed to account for the factsa "sexual theory of children" . These considerations clear the way for the following question: does not disavowalwhose consequences in reality are so obviousbear upon a factor which founds human reality rather than upon a hypothetical "fact of perception"? (See also "Foreclosure".) (Lap67 120)Or we might ask: what is Freud disavowing when he refuses to see the non-reality of castration? For Lacan, psychosis is the product of foreclosure: a radical repudiation of the truth of castration and the reality it founds. Laplanche and Pontalis begin to ask the questions that subvert this castration truth, but seem incapable of seeing the idea that "woman is castrated" as a projection of the "hom(m)osexuality" of psychoanalysis, and itself a disavowal of difference beyond (op)positionality. Castration is the disavowal of sexual difference, and here I mean sexual difference beyond the traditional binary of male/female. In other words, this binary of "sexual difference" is itself a disavowal of difference, a reduction of something totally other to an idealized binary. Freuds reduction of what is totally other to man/woman is then followed by a reduction of woman to castration, so we are left with two (op)positions (having/not having) of One sex: hom(m)osexuality. Lacans introduction of foreclosure and his definition of the Real in terms of woman and God in Encore belies the rigidness of the "castration-truth" of his psychoanalysis: in many ways, he takes this logic of lack to its end. Lacans psychotic lacks the "anchoring point" that stops the supposed sliding of signifiersin the Symbolic, but then reduces this sliding and its "chaos" to a specific absence "related to a conceivable presence": "trauma"-structure. Lacans position, however, is clearly one of disavowal trying to maintain an Aufhebung that preserves mutually exclusive opposites since the Symbolic is both fixed as the law of the father and in motion as the maternal other. Freuds position is also consistently one of disavowal with respect to sexual difference, superstition, and contingencyand, by extension, the uncanny. His disavowal, and the subsequent splitting of the PP, concerns his own position in relation to these themes. Castration logic is necessarily doubly split with relation to woman: "she" is both present (as (op)positional other) and absent (with respect to the One of hom(m)osexuality). She is " Logo-phonocentrism is not a philosophical or historical error which the history of philosophy, of the West, that is, of the world, would have rushed into pathologically, but is rather a necessary, and necessarily finite, movement and structure: the history of the possibility of symbolism in general (before the distinction between man and animal, and even before the distinction between the living and the nonliving); the history of différance, history as différance which finds in philosophy as episteme, in the European form of the metaphysical or onto-theological project, the privileged manifestation, with worldwide dominance, of dissimulation, of general censorship of the text in general. (Der78 197)The line through the Lacanian " The phallic mother is the fetishists compromise figure, the perverse ego ideal. From an oedipal position, however, this figure is psychotic: it threatens the patrocentrism of oedipal positionality based on the male/female binary and is therefore still associated with castration with respect to the oedipal One this binary servesthat is, even though the phallic mother is intended to nullify the very issue of castration. The phallic mother short-circuits the actual phallic function by mixing the two poles of the binary, which constitutes "her" form of castration for the oedipal One. Though it attempts to deal with castration, the "problem" of the One, the phallic mother subverts the very binary foundation that castration "solves" by providing an identity-difference term. The fetishists "solution" subverts the "solution" of the oedipal One by subverting the binary of male/female, which thus makes the fetishist seem psychotic to the oedipal subject. The difference between the oedipal One and the fetishist is that the former relies on the logic of lack and the actual phallic function to achieve his position (or her (non)position), whereas the fetishist relies on a logic of disavowal with respect to castration. The oedipal One and the actual phallic function, however, also rely on a logic of disavowal, but with respect to the presence and absence of woman, rather than the presence or absence of the maternal phallus. Despite these differences, both positions suffer from a splitting of the ego since both rely on a logic of disavowal: "solutions." Whereas the phallic mother is a non-solution because it disrupts "castration-truth," the "hysteric" and " The phallic mother is a psychotic and destabilizing figure within an oedipal patriarchy, and therefore cannot be the ideal of Freuds masterplot. The lure of this figure, however, is the lure of an even more totalizing masterplot than that which can be had within the oedipal "solution." Freud associates this "solution" with science and its acceptance of chance, and this chance provides the limit of what the masterplot can master, the limit of the PP: chance as what is beyond the PP. The animistic beliefs of superstition, associated with the primitive of Man/man, and therefore with the mother, and the Gestalt of the mother-infant monad/dyad, combine with the phallocentrism of Freuds oedipal patriarchy to make the phallic mother a figure combining phallic totality and maternal totality. Freuds fantasy of combining occultism and psychoanalysis can be construed as a fantasy of absolute mastery with no loss: like a fetishists fantasy of total determinism, with no loss, but one that is ultimately split along the dividing line of a disavowal. Another way of conceptualizing this dividing line is with respect to the subject-object split required in the logic of phallic mastery, and the mise en abyme of what appears as a fusion with the mother from an oedipal positionaccepting the truth of "animistic beliefs" as regressing back into fusion with the mother. Jouissance would be both the pleasure of the "oceanic feeling" of such a "(dis)solution" and the terror of falling into the void. From a phallic position, such a fall would be a castration, a death. next > |
Copyright 2000 by Eric W. Anders |